Download Meditations By Marcus Aurelius Pdf
Discover the world's research
- 20+ million members
- 135+ million publications
- 700k+ research projects
Join for free
The Meditations of Marcus Aurelius: Selections Annotated and Explained. Annotation by Russell
McNeil, translation by George Long. Woodstock, VT: Skylight Paths, 2007.
In this slim book of annotated selections from the Meditations, Russell McNeil makes the mind
of the Stoic Roman philosopher-emperor Marcus Aurelius stunningly accessible to the modern
reader. The foregoing sentence may seem paradoxical, because Marcus Aurelius is arguably the
most accessible of ancient philosophers, and his masterpiece, the Meditations (the original work
lacks a title, and it has also been called Marcus Aurelius to Himself) has remained in publication
almost since its composition, and still sells well in a number of translations in a variety of
languages today. What McNeil has accomplished is a selection and reassembly of the
disconnected fragments that make up the accepted text into parts that exhibit a rational
arrangement by subjects. These parts have to do with the Stoic ideas of happiness, virtue, the
body, the mind, method, the environment, daily practice, and society.
The reader must know at the outset that this edition is not a new translation of the
Meditations. McNeil has used the authoritative edition of the 1862 translation by the British
scholar George Long, but has modernized and Americanized Long's Victorian English, carefully
eliding language that might seem sexist or politically incorrect these days. The result is clear and
readable, although without turning to Long and the original Greek (the language in which the
well-educated emperor chose to write his own reflections), one can never be sure if Marcus
Aurelius was indeed as smooth as McNeil makes him sound. Also, this is not strictly speaking a
commentary on the Meditations, since McNeil's annotations are not intended only to explain the
thoughts and syntax of the author, but also to expand on the ideas encountered in the text and to
expound on their relevance to the reader and to modern issues. The book is not only a competent
scholarly treatment of an ancient philosophical text, but beyond that a tract written by an
articulate and convincing modern Stoic. McNeil makes no attempt to conceal the fact that he
finds the Stoicism of Marcus Aurelius valuable as a guide to personal and social thought and
action. This reviewer must make a brief quibble before proceeding further. McNeil refers to the
philosopher by the name "Aurelius" almost throughout the book, and I found this annoying. All
modern classical scholars and historians call him "Marcus," which was the only one of his many
names that was used throughout his life. "Aurelius" is the name of his Roman proletarian gens,
and should always be used in combination with his nomen (Marcus). In the Meditations he, when
referring to himself by name, uses his adoptive father's name, Antoninus. In the rest of this
review, then, the reader will know whom I mean when I mention "Marcus."
Marcus has a lot to say about nature. The word appears constantly in his writing, and has
a central role in the structure of his philosophy. McNeil notes this with approval, and envisions
Marcus as a forerunner of the ideas of "nature as a single ecosystem" (p. xxii) and "an ancient
and universal Gaia ecology" (p. 158). But do even the selections in this volume support such an
extension of Stoic ideas? At times it seems so. Marcus speaks of "The nature of which you are
part" (p. 155) and "The continuous spinning of the web and the interconnections in all of its
parts" (p. 159). His most constant concern, however, is with the only thing over which we have
any control: our opinion (attitude). It is that which we must bring into accord with nature, and the
nature with which we must be most concerned is our own human nature. True enough, in Stoic
thought human nature is inextricably linked with the natural law that governs the universe.
Marcus constantly warns us to act in accord with nature, and to do nothing against nature. In this
effort, reason will be our guide. But reason tells us that we can do nothing against nature:
"Nothing can happen to a man or woman which is not according to the nature of a human being"
(p. 203). Nature is absolute necessity; nothing can happen against nature. What, then, is the
import of Marcus' warning that we must do nothing against nature? It is a warning against false
opinion. Opinion guided by reason is true opinion, and all other opinion is false opinion. If we
act following false opinion, we act as it were against nature, and the result will be pain, anger,
depression, and other bad things for ourselves. Nothing from outside can hurt us, only the false
opinion we have can hurt us. The cure is reason (philosophy) and the true opinion it will provide.
Then what about environmental problems such as climate change? McNeil says that
Marcus would "tell us that it is within our intellectual power to see this looming misfortune as an
opportunity to restore the harmony between nature and humanity that is the basis of human
purpose" (p. 166). But would he, really? It seems to me that Marcus would say that climate
change is something that comes from outside, and therefore cannot harm us. What could harm us
is a false opinion of it. Also, Marcus would say that we can do nothing about climate change, and
that therefore it should not concern us. It is one of those many things, like violence done to us by
others, or poverty, or sexual abuse, which cannot really harm us in our inmost selves and is
therefore neither good nor evil. So is there no Stoic response to climate change that modern
humans can find at all satisfying? I think there is. McNeil constantly emphasizes Marcus'
insistence on love as a basic principle, and that we are by nature social beings: "The prime
principle then in the rational constitution is the social." (p.147). If climate change is harming
fellow members of our community (and if Marcus could be enlightened by the modern scientific
understanding of anthropogenic causes of climate change), Marcus could well say that we ought
to do the various things that science indicates may at least mitigate the magnitude and impact of
climate change as an act of benevolence toward our fellow rational beings. He does say that even
within the broad spectrum of those things that are neither good nor evil, such actions are
rationally indicated and in accord with nature. The exercise of virtue is personal good. As in
feeding the hungry, however, our own personal good must be our concern. Feeding the hungry
does them no good in itself, since it does not teach them true opinion.
Even if one is not convinced by this book to adopt Stoic principles for oneself, one can
admire it as a work of scholarship and a valuable explanation of an ancient philosophy that has
lasting influences in today's intellectual world. There are very few errors in matters of fact, but
one at least calls for correction. McNeil, in explaining Marcus' sense of the vast size of the Earth
compared to an individual human inhabitant, refers to Eratosthenes' measurement of the size of
the terrestrial globe (p. 26). He did this by measuring the angles (not the lengths) of shadows cast
by vertical poles in two distant locations (they did not have to be of the same height, and in a
version of the story, one location was a well, not a pole). This occurred at noon on the same day,
the summer solstice (not when the Sun was at the zenith in each spot, but only in the southern
one). McNeil says one pole was in Alexandria (correct) and the other in Cyrene in modern-day
Libya—about 500 miles due south. A glance at the map shows this to be impossible, since
Cyrene is way off to the west. The correct identification of the second place is Syene at the First
Cataract, which corresponds to modern Aswan in Upper Egypt. Eratosthenes' solution for the
Earth's circumference is argued because there are conflicting values for the length of the Greek
stadium, the unit of distance, but some estimates are closer to the true girth of the globe than the
one McNeil gives.
In representing the character of MA, McNeil is uniformly laudatory and when flaws
appear that are inescapable for any imperfect human leader, defensive. If Marcus despised the
bloody spectacles of the Roman arena, why did he do nothing to stop them? McNeil says that
Marcus detested war, spent much of his reign fighting the northern barbarians out of defensive
necessity, and did not engage in wars of expansion or conquest. But when he erected his notable
public monument, the Column of MA, which portrays his battles in a spiral relief, he patterned it
exactly after the Column of Trajan, his predecessor, which portrays the aggressive annexation of
Dacia (modern Romania). McNeil says Marcus Aurelius favored representative democracy, but
in the relevant passage Marcus says only that a king should respect the freedom of subjects.
Although McNeil portrays him as lenient toward those who held other ideas (but not self-serving
egoists), Marcus Aurelius did not extend toleration to the Christians. McNeil presents several
excuses for this (p. 212), but nonetheless there were bloody persecutions during his reign in
Lugdunum and Vienne, and Marcus did not intervene. This was a source of confusion to
Christian historians such as Eusebius, who thought that good emperors like Marcus Aurelius had
not been persecutors, but found evidence to the contrary. None of this invalidates Marcus' Stoic
ideals, of course. It only shows that he did not consistently embody them, a fact that McNeil is
reluctant to admit.
These omissions are forgivable, however, in an editor who has manifest sympathy with
his subject and a profound understanding of the many dimensions of the Stoic worldview.
McNeil is a fine writer who can introduce the reader who has little background in the classics to
one of the most temperate and consoling philosophers of all time. In a period of history when
many philosophers, Neo-Platonists and others, valued pure spirit above such physical things as
the body and the natural environment, Marcus Aurelius insisted on the integration of human
inner life with nature and insisted that the creations of nature were at least as beautiful as the
works of art. We still have much to learn from him, and Russell McNeil's eloquent book can help
us in that task.
J. Donald Hughes University of Denver
Use of "Aurelius" as name
A commitment to stoicism
Loved him
Pneuma and logos
Reason
Perfection of nature's laws = beauty
We ought to live according to nature
The Divinity of Nature
Zeno xxiii
Reason, not faith
Cyclical universe
Love is attraction to beauty
Knowledge of nature
McNeil avoids Long's sexist language, but Nature remains feminine
1 The Promise of Stoicism
The logos within
We seek retreats—retire into your own soul
Desiring, spirited, reasoning 7
Natural unity: the ruling principle of nature
Sin is any action contrary to nature
(No! Sin is action resulting from false opinion)
Is the soul material? 15
GUTs and TOEs 16
"Understanding is an opinion acquired through the use of reason. This sort of opinion can lead to
the exercise of virtue… and this is personal good." 18
There is nothing elitist about Stoicism.
Soon you will be ash 25
The whole earth is a point 27
Syene (he thinks it is Cyrene) is not in Libya! Explanation of Eratosthenes not clear. 26
Entropy
"Whatever happens, happens for the best." 34
McNeil takes refuge in the Heisenberg principle 34
2 Stoicism and Virtue 37
Love
Respect nature 45
3 Stoicism and Vice 57
No need for a war on terror 58
"If you do not know what the world is, you know not where you are." 65
"You are like a priest and minister of nature." 75
"They are far less likely to worry about physical or economic security when dealing with a
major… environmental crisis." 80 The environmental crisis is noted by McNeil, not Marcus.
4 Stoicism and the Body 87
You are formed by nature to bear everything 95
It is your interest or duty to bear it
Toleration and freedom of expression 96
Epicurus and pain
Death ends the discursive movements of the thoughts 105
Is there another kind of sensation after death? 107
We are supposed to love society, but we can't stand our stupid neighbors! 108
5 Stoicism and the Mind 113
World-soul has corporeal nature 114
Say more about Socrates 116
Knowing yourself: mind, not body
We are able to understand nature and its laws
The ruling intelligence 121
Works of art are only called beautiful 123
The beauty of nature and her works: ripe fruit, lion's eyebrows, boars' foam 125
Art imitates nature
False opinions disturb the soul 126
6 The Method of Stoicism 129
Abandon all discontent and blame 132
The consolation of philosophy (loving wisdom) 136
He is laying foundations for the study of science (?) 142
"The prime principle then in the rational constitution is the social." 147
The rational is superior to the animal
We are deeply integrated within the perfect fabric of nature (McNeil)
7 Stoicism and the Environment 151
The Seeds of Logos
Failure to cite sources – spermatikoi logoi
Avoids meaning of "abuse" 153
"The nature of which you are part" 155
Personal fulfillment or the environment 154
Harmonizing with nature 157
"O Nature: from you are all things, in you are all things, to you all things return." 157
The universe as one living being 159
Compared with Lovelock 158
"The continuous spinning of the web and the interconnections in all of its parts" 159
"An ancient and universal Gaia ecology" 158
The sea is a drop, Athos a clod
All things are bonded with one another 163
McNeill says the auto engine is unnatural but the fuel cell is natural. 162
Recycling?
"Nature and climate change" has nothing to say about that.
Animals devoid of reason, but have love
Abuse 166
Nature is necessity 167 (McNeil avoids the implications)
8 The Practice of Stoicism 169
The wrestler's art 171
Prayer?
Love the art you have learned
Compassion for wrongdoers
Labor not contrary to (your) nature 177
Anger management 181
"Act with justice in all your actions in accordance with the universal nature" 191
Nothing in this world can ever cause us harm
"Nothing can happen to a man or woman which is not according to the nature of a human being"
203
Statelessness 206
9 Society and Government in Stoicism 209
McNeil pretends that Marcus Aurelius was a democrat 210
Same law for all, equal rights, freedom of speech 211
Condemned Christianity 212
Universe a concourse of atoms, or nature is a system 217
Heraclitus and logos 218
Those who oppose play a part in nature's plan
"The state will never suffer real harm, because the law and order of the universe—the ruling
intelligence—is impervious to harm. 225-225
Show whoever causes harm where the error is 227
Marcus Aurelius did not conduct expansionary campaigns or wars of aggression 226
(But he approved of Trajan's Dacian campaigns ¥)!
Opposition to dissent 229
ResearchGate has not been able to resolve any citations for this publication.
ResearchGate has not been able to resolve any references for this publication.
Posted by: carmelacarmelaschleimere0269955.blogspot.com
Source: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/250015316_The_Meditations_of_Marcus_Aurelius_Selections_Annotated_and_Explained_annotation_by_Russell_McNeil
Post a Comment for "Download Meditations By Marcus Aurelius Pdf"